Karl Marx and the Death Penalty . Robert M. Bohm

Karl Marx and the Death Penalty

Robert M. Bohm

Published online: 25 September 2008

_ Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Abstract This study is a Marxist analysis of capital punishment or the death penalty. The

only detailed treatment of the subject by Marx appeared in an article published in the New

York Daily Tribune, February 18, 1853, and that treatment was only a sketch. Thus, the

following study is an attempt to suggest what a reading of Marx may contribute to an

understanding of capital punishment. I conclude that abolition of the death penalty does not

need a Marxist justification, but a Marxist justification adds to the many arguments for that

course of action.

Introduction

It is remarkable that Karl Marx, who wrote so little about crime and punishment, has had

such an extraordinary influence on the subjects. His work has inspired a voluminous

literature of Marxist (or radical or critical) criminology. Still, that Marxist criminological

literature is conspicuous for its relative dearth of capital-punishment analysis. The purpose

of this study is to suggest what a reading of Marx may contribute to an understanding of

capital punishment.

Marx on the Death Penalty

Marx’s most detailed thoughts on capital punishment appeared in an article published in

the New York Daily Tribune, February 18, 1853 (Marx 1853). He constructed the article in

the following way. First, he provided examples of cases that showed that the death penalty

had a counter-deterrent or brutalizing effect; that is, that executions cause murders. He also

presented data showing that murders and suicides ‘‘follow closely the execution of

R. M. Bohm (&)

Department of Criminal Justice and Legal Studies, University of Central Florida, Orlando,

FL 32816, USA

e-mail: rbohm@mail.ucf.edu

 

Crit Crim (2008) 16:285–291

DOI 10.1007/s10612-008-9062-8

criminals.’’ Marx was not the first to observe this counter-deterrent effect, but he was one

of the earliest to write about it. Dr. Benjamin Rush, for example, the putative founder of

the American death penalty abolitionist movement, noted in the late eighteenth century that

capital punishment might increase crime (Filler 1967, p. 106; Gorecki 1983, p. 85).

As for the deterrent effect of punishment, Marx noted that ‘‘since Cain the world has

been neither intimidated or [sic] ameliorated by punishment.’’ Again, Marx was not the

first to question the deterrent effect of capital punishment, but he was an early skeptic. His

views have subsequently been validated. According to U.S. Supreme Court Justice John

Paul Stevens in his recent opinion in Baze v. Rees (553 U.S. __, 2008): ‘‘Despite 30 years

of empirical research in the area, there remains no reliable statistical evidence that capital

punishment in fact deters potential offenders.’’ In 1989, following a comprehensive review

of death penalty research by a panel of distinguished scholars, the American Society of

Criminology passed a resolution condemning capital punishment and calling for its abolition.

Among the reasons for the Society’s position was the absence of ‘‘consistent

evidence of crime deterrence through execution’’ (Petersilia 1990, p. 1). A recent survey of

67 current and past presidents of the top three criminology professional organizations—the

American Society of Criminology, the Academy of Criminal Justice Sciences, and the Law

and Society Association—found that about 80% of them believe that the death penalty is

no greater a deterrent to homicide than long imprisonment’’ (Radelet and Akers 1996).

This latter observation focuses on capital punishment’s marginal deterrent effect; that is,

whether capital punishment has a greater deterrent effect than non-capital punishments

such as life imprisonment without opportunity for parole. There is no evidence that capital

punishment has a marginal deterrent effect.

Second, Marx criticized both Kant and Hegel’s German idealism regarding their beliefs

about free will and self-determination. Marx’s ontology was different. In The German

Ideology, Marx wrote, ‘‘It is clear … that individuals certainly make one another, physically

and mentally, but do not make themselves’’ (Marx and Engels 1976, pp. 55–56,

emphasis in original). In the article, Marx also cited favorably the work of the positivist

and ‘‘moral statistician’’ Adolphe Quetelet, who showed the regularity of both the amount

and type of crime in a ‘‘modern bourgeois society’’ (referring to France and the United

States in the early nineteenth century). It was Quetelet, incidentally, that observed early on

that a key factor in violent crime was ‘‘relative poverty,’’ where there is great inequality

between poverty and wealth in the same area. According to Quetelet, relative poverty

incited people through jealousy to commit violent crimes. This was especially true, surmised

Quetelet, where changing economic conditions caused the impoverishment of some

people while others retained their wealth (Taylor et al. 1974, pp. 37–38; Vold and Bernard

1986, pp. 131–132). Quetelet’s formulation is consistent with Marxist analysis; furthermore,

the idea that ‘‘relative poverty’’ or ‘‘relative deprivation’’ is a cause of crime has

been adopted by current critical or Marxist criminologists (see, for example, Young 1997,

p. 30).

Third, Marx argued that ‘‘punishment is nothing but a means of society to defend itself

against the infraction of its vital conditions, whatever may be their character.’’ He then

quipped, taking a poke at capitalism, ‘‘is there not a necessity for deeply reflecting upon an

alteration of the system that breeds these crimes, instead of glorifying the hangman who

executes a lot of criminals to make room only for the supply of new ones?’’ Marx

maintained that one would be hard pressed to find a use for capital punishment in a society

‘‘glorying in its civilization.’’ In that respect, he shared the viewpoint, attributed to both

Fyodor Dostoevsky and Winston Churchill, that: ‘‘The mood and temper of the public with

286 R. M. Bohm

 

regard to the treatment of crime and criminals is one of the most unfailing tests of the

civilization of any country.’’

Marx believed that capitalism produces an amount and type of crime that it punishes.

One of the roles of the state is to determine guilt and administer punishment. Capital

punishment is the state’s ultimate sanction and means of coercion and is generally reserved

for the most heinous crimes, as defined by the state, but not necessarily the most serious

harms. Marx apparently expected heinous crime in capitalist societies and the death

penalty as a means by which the capitalist state would deal with it.

Death-Eligible Crime

Following Friedrich Engels’ description of the causes of crime in The Condition of the

Working Class in England (1968, pp. 145–146), Marxist criminologists have argued

that ‘‘senseless’’ and heinous violent crime—the type of crime most likely to be deatheligible—

is a product of the demoralizing and brutalizing conditions under which many

people are forced to live in a capitalist society. As criminologists Taylor, Walton, and

Young explain, ‘‘It is not that man behaves as an animal because of his ‘nature’ [under

capitalism]: it is that he is not fundamentally allowed by virtue of the social arrangements

of production to do otherwise’’ (1975, p. 23). Recent estimates provide support for this

contention. Nationwide, about 40% of all capital indictments are for felony murder, i.e., a

murder committed during the commission of another felony such as armed robbery

(Walker 2006), and many other death-eligible murders are the result of ‘‘collateral

damage’’ in the illicit drug trade.

Not long ago, criminologist Elliott Currie specified seven elements of ‘‘market societies’’

or ‘‘capitalist societies’’ that he believed, in combination, are likely to breed serious

violent crime. They are:

(1) ‘‘the progressive destruction of livelihood’’ (the absence of steady well-paying work);

(2) ‘‘the growth of extremes of economic inequality and material deprivation’’;

(3) ‘‘the withdrawal of public services and supports, especially for families and

children’’;

(4) ‘‘the erosion of informal and communal networks of mutual support, supervision, and

care’’;

(5) ‘‘the spread of a materialistic, neglectful, and ‘hard’ culture’’ (the exaltation of ‘‘often

brutal individual competition and consumption over the values of community,

contribution, and productive work’’);

(6) ‘‘the unregulated marketing of the technology of violence’’ (the absence of public

regulation of firearms); and, not least

(7) ‘‘the weakening of social and political alternatives’’ (which inhibits people most ‘‘at

risk’’ from defining their problems in collective terms and envisioning a collective

response) (Currie 1997a; also see Currie 1997b).

Although one may agree with the Marxist analysis that capitalist societies breed serious

violent crime, it does not necessarily follow that capitalist societies must respond to serious

violent crime with capital punishment, as history clearly demonstrates. Nor is it to suggest

that state-socialist societies should be free of serious violent crime, as history also attests.

Rather, for Marxist criminologists, compared to capitalist societies, state-socialist societies

should have a different amount and type of serious violent crime because of the less intense

class struggle in state-socialist societies (see Chambliss 1976, p. 9). State-socialist

Karl Marx and the Death Penalty 287

 

societies, especially in their early transitional years, are likely to experience some residual

‘‘bourgeois crime’’ and capital punishment. History also demonstrates the use of capital

punishment by new leaders of state-socialist societies to rid themselves of their political

enemies. However, once state-socialist societies are more entrenched, they often abolish

capital punishment, at least for short periods of time. For example, the Second Congress of

Soviets abolished the death penalty in November 1917, only to reinstate it by 1922; even

Stalin repealed the death penalty in 1947, but reinstated it in 1950 for political crimes

(Caffentzis 2000).

Species-Beings and Capital Punishment

For Marx, state socialism is only a transitional stage to communism, as capitalism is a

transitional stage to socialism. Marx’s vision was that in the higher stages of a statelesscommunist

society (Marx’s ‘‘withering away of the state’’), there would be no need for

capital punishment (a tool of the state) because oppositional classes and ‘‘bourgeois

criminality’’ would disappear and human beings would be ‘‘species-beings.’’ Marx

assumed that human beings were inherently good (a la Rousseau) and that society corrupted

them. Even if human beings were simply a product of their experiences (a la Locke),

a corrupt society would still corrupt many of them.

An interesting question is: what is it about ‘‘species-being’’ that makes capital punishment

superfluous? Marx appropriated the concept of ‘‘species-being’’ from German

philosopher Ludwig Feuerbach, who, in The Essence of Christianity, wrote that what

distinguishes human beings from animals is not consciousness per se but rather a particular

kind of consciousness. This ‘‘human consciousness’’ is not just consciousness of the

individual as an individual, but also the consciousness of an individual as a member of the

human species whose ‘‘human essence’’ is the same as that of other human beings

(Bottomore 1963, p. 13, n. 2). Marx added to Feurbach’s original formulation the belief

that human beings are only living and acting authentically, i.e., in accordance with their

nature, when they are deliberately living and acting as ‘‘species-beings’’ or ‘‘social beings’’

(Bottomore 1963, p. 13, n. 2). In his essay, ‘‘On the Jewish Question,’’ Marx wrote that in

capitalist societies human beings are far from ‘‘species-beings.’’ In capitalist societies,

human beings are egoistic, separated from the community, withdrawn into themselves,

wholly preoccupied with their private interest, and act in accordance with their private

caprice (Bottomore 1963, p. 26). The only bond between human beings in capitalist

societies is natural necessity, need and private interest, the preservation of their property,

and their egoistic selves (Bottomore 1963, p. 26). In the Economic and Philosophical

Manuscripts, Marx wrote about alienated labor (in capitalist societies). It is here that Marx

explains that alienated labor alienates nature from human beings; alienates human beings

from themselves, from their own active functions, their life activities; and, in so doing,

alienates human beings from each other, their species (Bottomore 1963, p. 127). For Marx,

alienated labor is characterized by work that:

(1) ‘‘is external to the worker, that it is not part of his nature; and that consequently, he

does not fulfil [sic] himself in his work but denies himself, has a feeling of misery

rather than well-being, does not develop freely his mental and physical energies but is

physically exhausted and mentally debased’’;

(2) ‘‘his work is not voluntary but imposed, forced labour. It is not the satisfaction of a

need, but only a means for satisfying other needs. Its alien character is clearly shown

288 R. M. Bohm

 

by the fact that as soon as there is no physical or other compulsion it is avoided like

the plague’’;

(3) ‘‘the external character of work for the worker is shown by the fact it is not his own

work but work for someone else, that in work he does not belong to himself but to

another person’’ (Bottomore 1963, pp. 124–125, emphases in original).

Marx concludes that human beings (workers) in capitalist societies feel freely active only

in their animal functions—eating, drinking and procreating, or at most in their dwellings

and in personal adornment—while in their human functions, they are reduced to animals

(Bottomore 1963, p. 125). Under such conditions, serious violent crime is not surprising.

Communism and Capital Punishment

For Marx, ‘‘communism is the positive abolition of private property’’ and, for the purposes

of this analysis, ‘‘of human self-alienation … . It is, therefore, the return of man himself as

a social, i.e., really human, being, a complete and conscious return which assimilates all

the wealth of previous development’’ (Bottomore 1963, p. 155, emphasis in original).

Communism, writes Marx, ‘‘is the definitive resolution of the antagonism between man and

nature, and between man and man. It is the true solution of the conflict between existence

and essence, between objectification and self-affirmation, between freedom and necessity,

between individual and species’’ (Bottomore 1963, p. 155, emphasis in original). In a

communist society, according to Marx, ‘‘competition as we know it has given way to

cooperation as we have still to learn about it’’ (Ollman 1976, p. 106).

A communist society would have no need for capital punishment and no state to

administer it. Capital punishment would also be counterproductive in the transition from a

state-socialist society to a communist society because, during the transition, capital

offenders would play an important, constructive and educational role (see Gordon 1976,

p. 210). During the transition, capital offenders ‘‘would be treated in the ways that many

families deal with those family members who betray the family trust’’ (Gordon 1976,

p. 210). Society would admit its collective failure and, with the help of the offender, seek

ways to reform the total community (see Gordon 1976, p. 210).

Currie believes that, at present, the most promising lever of change and, at the same

time, the most effective means to significantly reduce serious violent crime, is ‘‘full

employment at socially meaningful work at good wages, and with reasonable hours’’

(Currie 1997a, p. 168). Such a policy would require ‘‘substantially expanding employment

in the public and nonprofit sectors of the economy, and developing policies for worksharing

and reduction of work time’’ (Currie 1997a, p. 168). It is important to emphasize,

as Currie does, that full employment, etc., as a means to reduce serious violent crime is a

reform for the present (during the capitalist transition to socialism) and probably during

state-socialism as well. However, as I have argued elsewhere (Bohm 1984), it is not the

long-term solution; communism is.

Critique

If Marx expected capital punishment in capitalist societies, which it appears he did, he was

wrong. Nearly all advanced capitalist societies, with the notable exceptions of the United

States and Japan, have abandoned capital punishment, as have most state-socialist

Karl Marx and the Death Penalty 289

 

societies. Some prominent political and economic conservatives, such as George Will,

William F. Buckley, Jr., Pat Robertson, and Milton Friedman, have questioned the death

penalty because of what they perceive as the enormous waste of capital it consumes and the

havoc it wrecks on the administration of justice, among other reasons.

Critics of Marx can point to the use of capital punishment in so-called socialist or

communist nations, such as the former Soviet Union, China, North Korea, and Cuba.

However, none of those nations were or are truly socialist or communist, at least as Marx

had originally conceived the terms. It is unfair to look to the totalitarian nations that were

or are socialist or communist in name only for guidance in dealing with the crime and

punishment problems of capitalist societies.

Today, it probably makes little sense to speak of capitalist and socialist societies

anyway, because no pure societies of either type exist (they probably never did.). All

countries now manifest elements of both capitalism and socialism. In the United States, for

example, Social Security, Medicare, Medicaid, and other social programs, such as public

education, public libraries, public parks, and public highways, provided by federal, state,

and local governments are clearly socialistic. Even so-called corporate welfare, such as the

many subsidies and tax loopholes for corporations, is socialistic. At the beginning of the

twenty-first century, all countries have ‘‘mixed’’ economies, with elements of both capitalism

and socialism. Thus, it may make more sense to refer to capitalist-dominated

societies and socialist-dominated societies.

What may be occurring in the world at present is the transition of advanced

state-capitalist-dominated societies, such as the United States and Great Britain, to

state-socialist-dominated societies, and the transition of what are erroneously called statesocialist

societies, such as Russia and China, to the early stages of capitalism. The capitalist-

to-socialist transition was predicted by Marx, but Marx never dreamed that societies

would try to skip necessary stages of development, as was done in all supposedly statesocialist

or ‘‘state-communist’’ societies. The adoption of the free enterprise system

(capitalism) by former supposedly state-socialist or state-communist societies is simply the

result of a long overdue recognition by such societies that capitalism is a necessary

transitional stage, as Marx originally had argued.

Critics of Marx also contend that his communist vision is utopian. However, in The

German Ideology, Marx (and Engels) argued that communism is neither ‘‘a ‘state of

affairs’ which is to be established’’ or ‘‘an ‘ideal’ to which reality [will] have to adjust

itself,’’ but rather ‘‘the ‘real’ movement which abolishes the present state of things’’ (Marx

and Engels 1976, pp. 56–57). The reason communism is not utopian for Marx is because

the factors, in the absence of which communism is impossible, exist as potential within the

conditions now in existence. However, while ‘‘communist factors’’ may indeed exist as

potential within the conditions now in existence, Marx’s apparent belief that the potential

will inevitably be realized betrays his own idealism.

Conclusion

Abolition of the death penalty does not need a Marxist justification, but a Marxist justification

adds to the many arguments for that course of action. It is noteworthy in that regard

that one of the most politically conservative institutions in society—the Roman Catholic

Church—is one with the politically radical ideology of Marxism in opposing capital

punishment. If Marxists and the Pope can find common ground on the issue of capital

290 R. M. Bohm

 

punishment, then it seems inevitable that those in the middle of the two political extremes

eventually will also see the wisdom of abolishing the death penalty.

References

Bohm, R. M. (1984). Beyond employment: Toward a radical solution to the crime problem. Crime and

Social Justice, 21–22, 213–222.

Bottomore, T. B. (Ed.). (1963). Karl Marx: Early writings (T. B. Bottomore, Trans.). New York: McGraw-

Hill.

Caffentzis, G. (2000). Report on death penalty in Cuba dialogue. www.ocf.berkeley.edu/*marto/adpp/

cuba.htm. Accessed 10 Sept 2007.

Chambliss, W. J. (1976). Functional and conflict theories of crime: The heritage of Emile Durkheim and

Karl Marx. In W. J. Chambliss & M. Mankoff (Eds.), Whose law what order? (pp. 1–28). New York:

Wiley.

Currie, E. (1997a). Market, crime and community: Toward a mid-range theory of post-industrial violence.

Theoretical Criminology, 1, 147–172.

Currie, E. (1997b). Market society and social disorder. In B. D. MacLean & D. Milovanovic (Eds.), Thinking

critically about crime (pp. 37–42). Vancouver, BC: Collective Press.

Engels, F. (1968). The condition of the working class in England (W.O. Henderson & W. H. Chaloner,

Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Filler, L. (1967). Movements to abolish the death penalty in the United States. In T. Sellin (Ed.), Capital

punishment (pp. 104–122). New York: Harper & Row.

Gordon, D. M. (1976). Class and the economics of crime. In W. J. Chambliss & M. Mankoff (Eds.), Whose

law what order? (pp. 193–214). New York: Wiley.

Gorecki, J. (1983). Capital punishment: Criminal law and social evolution. New York: Columbia University

Press.

Marx, K. (1853). New York Daily Tribune article on the death penalty. www.marxists.org/archive/

marx/works/1853/02/18.htm.

Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1976). The German ideology. New York: International.

Ollman, B. (1976). Alienation (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Petersilia, J. (1990). Death penalty resolution debated and endorsed. The Criminologist, 15, 1.

Radelet, M. L., & Akers, R. L. (1996). Deterrence and the death penalty: The view of the experts. Journal of

Criminal Law and Criminology, 87, 1–16.

Taylor, I., Walton, P., & Young, J. (1974). The new criminology: For a social theory of deviance. New

York: Harper and Row.

Vold, G. B., & Bernard, T. J. (1986). Theoretical criminology (3rd ed.). New York: Oxford.

Walker, R. N. (2006). How the malfunctioning death penalty challenges the criminal justice system.

Judicature, 89, 265–268.

Young, J. (1997). Left realism: The basics. In B. D. MacLean & D. Milovanovic

 

http://www2.cohpa.ucf.edu/crim.jus/documents/BohmKarlMarxandthedeathpenalty.pdf

Questa voce è stata pubblicata in Marx e C. e contrassegnata con , . Contrassegna il permalink.